Showing posts with label Sharon Rawlette. Show all posts
Showing posts with label Sharon Rawlette. Show all posts

Friday, August 1, 2025

Why I don't believe in subjectivism

Part 1: Travis Talks is right about some things
 
The Substack Travis Talks made a post titled "Objections to Subjectivism Are Terrible" (https://travistalks.substack.com/p/objections-to-subjectivism-are-terrible). In this post are many important takeaways that I agree with, including:
  • If someone says something horrible like: "The Holocaust was good", it's important to distinguish between the subjective proposition "I approve of the Holocaust" (which is a true statement for a Nazi) versus the objective proposition "The Holocaust was good in such a way that if someone doesn't find the Holocaust to be good then they are mistaken" (which is a false statement). Failing to make this distinction can lead to 'normative entanglement' (see: https://www.lanceindependent.com/p/normative-entanglement-a-new-name-for-an-old-rhetorical-trick).
  • Agent Relativism vs Appraiser Relativism: The former view says that what is in fact right or wrong is relative to individual standards. The latter view says that when a person says "x is wrong", they just mean "I disapprove x." So we can say that agent relativism is normative (about what is in fact morally right or wrong) while appraiser relativism is descriptive (about what people in fact mean when they make moral claims).
As the post shows, many objections to subjectivism trade on failures to understand distinctions such as these.
 
Note: My metaethical views are very much in progress; this is an exercise to help work out my thoughts. Currently, I don't accept the existence of categorical imperatives or irreducible normative properties, but I do accept objective value facts (facts about what is good, bad, better, valuable, worthless, etc.) and the objective descriptive truth of some 'should' and 'ought' claims. So I'm currently convinced of some form of descriptive moral realism while unconvinced of prescriptive moral realism. My lack of an acceptance of irreducible normative properties is something I have in common with subjectivists, and it may turn out that what I say here is compatible with some form of subjectivism or, like the objections responded to in the Substack post, trades on misunderstandings on what subjectivists are actually committed to. One of the core issues of this discussion, one I will be revisiting in future posts, is what it means to make a judgment, how our experiences relate to judgments, and what it means for the truth of a claim to be dependent or independent of judgment.
 
Part 2: Why I don't believe in subjectivism
 
This leads into an important quote from the Substack post:
 
"Subjectivism is not in the business of telling you what sorts of things are right or wrong. It's in the business of telling you what people are doing when they say things are right or wrong."
 
And what are people doing when they claim that an action is morally right or wrong, per subjectivism? They are voicing personal disapproval, and, key point here: They are not voicing a recognition of the stance-independent rightness or wrongness of an action.
 
And that's my key point: I am voicing a recognition of the stance-independent rightness or wrongness of an action when I make a moral claim.
 
Even if some people (or even if most people, or even if all other people besides me) mean "I disapprove of x" when they say "x is wrong", I am an exception to this description. That's not what I mean when I say "x is wrong."
 
Here is what I take to be a non-subjective, objective, judgment-independent, stance-independent (these are all synonyms) claim:
 
(S) Kaitlin Armstrong should not have killed Moriah Wilson.
 
(W) Kaitlin Armstrong killing Moriah Wilson was wrong (incorrect, not right, mistaken, evil).
 
(Free will stuff: Is Armstrong blameworthy in the sense that she is liable for just deserts in the form of retributive punishment? I believe not, because I reject the notion of free will. Is Armstrong morally blameworthy in the sense that I can conclude that Armstrong qua experiencer is bad or evil? I don't think it makes any sense to view a person as a subject of experiences in evaluative terms. Is Armstrong critically blameworthy in the sense that what she has [in terms of virtue, reasoning, wisdom, reasons for actions, etc.] is of poor quality? Yes; it does make sense to view the accidental properties of persons in evaluative terms [e.g. my athleticism is an accidental property of me and it's entirely warranted to view its quality as, uh, non-Olympic, to put it nicely]. Is Armstrong qua experiencer unlucky to have these things in poor quality? Yes.)
 
When philosophers talk about tortured babies or murder, I bet that they usually aren't trying to imagine what these things look like. To make things a bit easier to imagine for us, here are a few details of the Wilson murder: 
  • Armstrong apparently killed Wilson out of jealousy. 
  • Wilson was shot twice in the head and once in the chest.  
  • Prosecutor Rick Jones says Wilson screamed in terror before being shot, based on surveillance footage (https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=15DY0NcfyLM).
  • Caitlin Cash, friend of Moriah Wilson, said the following in her victim impact statement: "So many people in this room have lost so much. I'm angry. At you. At the utter tragic nature. At the senselessness. At not being able to hear Mo's voice again. I feel deep sadness for the road ahead" (https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=go186wdXS04).
  • Moriah Wilson's mother said the following: "I hate what you did to my beautiful daughter. It was very selfish and cowardly. That violent act on May 11th. It was cowardly because you never chose to face her woman to woman in a civil conversation. She would have listened. She was an amazing listener. She would have cared about your feelings."
  • A KVUE article describes how Moriah Wilson's brother (Matt Wilson) broke into tears when he took the stand and was asked to speak about his sister (https://www.kvue.com/article/news/crime/kaitin-armstrong-trial-closing-arguments/269-7d7750ae-13e7-477e-a740-8ee80c09c796). Per that article, Matt Wilson said: "My sister had her life taken from her for no reason at all. She'll never ride a bike again, she'll never get married, never buy a home, have kids, never meet someone she loves ... I and my parents will never be able to see that happen and have her enjoy that life and build that life."
  • After Armstrong was sentenced to 90 years in prison, Moriah Wilson's father said the following to the press (https://www.courttv.com/title/mo-wilsons-dad-there-really-are-no-winners-here/): "There really are no winners here. This is not a time for celebration, but a time for prayer. A time to pray for our family, our friends, the Armstrong family, and their friends. This sad story is a perfect example of why integrity and honesty are crucial in our personal relationships, and how dishonesty can often lead to unintended consequences. Selfish manipulation, jealousy, and hatred never lead to positive outcomes. Violence is never a good way to solve personal issues. In fact, violence doesn't solve anything. It only leads to more suffering."
It's one thing to talk about murder in the abstract. It's another to talk about Kaitlin Armstrong murdering Moriah Wilson and the horror, tragedy, and thoughtlessness of the event, and the permanent damage done to the families and communities involved.  
 
Do I personally disapprove of Armstrong's killing of Wilson? Yes, and if you were to ask me why, I would give an answer beyond "I don't like it" or "It goes against my values", and there would be a further answer to the question of why I give that answer rather than another. But more on that later. First, when I say "Kaitlin Armstrong killing Moriah Wilson was wrong", do I merely mean to say that "I personally disapprove of Armstrong's killing of Wilson"? 
 
Not at all. Instead, I mean to say that "Kaitlin Armstrong killing Moriah Wilson fails to further [goal]."
 
We can substitute [goal] with something like "the goal of maximizing flourishing."
 
This is why when I make a claim of the pattern "x is wrong", I am not making an internal, subjective claim about my values or feelings. I am making an external, objective claim about how an action fails to further a goal.
 
It's almost certainly the case that Armstrong had a goal of living well, of not going to prison (she tried to evade capture multiple times), of not facing the kind of social backlash one faces when one becomes a murderer, and so on. In that case, by killing Moriah, Armstrong failed at her own goals.
 
So <Kaitlin Armstrong should not have killed Moriah Wilson> = <Killing Moriah Wilson fails to further the goals of living well, not going to prison, increasing one's virtue, building a good reputation and legacy for oneself, etc.>
 
And if Armstrong had empathetic goals (which Armstrong did not have), then killing Moriah Wilson fails to further the goal of maximizing the flourishing of Wilson and her family and friends, as well as that of Armstrong's own family and friends. If you understand the goodness of Moriah Wilson's (etc.) would-be flourishing, then you will have such an empathetic goal. If these empathetic goals were required to achieve Armstrong's more fundamental goals (say, the goal of not experiencing the judgment and shame of being on trial for murder), then Armstrong should have had these empathetic goals. In my view, 'should' picks out the action that best furthers a goal or is necessary to further a goal. So I'm not committing myself to some mysterious, irreducible normative property; I see 'should' statements as being descriptively true or false, describing which actions are best or necessary at furthering or achieving a goal.
 
So the killing of Moriah Wilson fails to maximize flourishing, and that is a true statement about the world and not just about myself or my personal feelings. It's true irrespective of anyone's judgment of its truth. When I say "the murder of Moriah Wilson fails to maximize flourishing", I am not saying "Armstrong killing Moriah Wilson? Yuck!", like the emotivist would claim, nor am I merely saying "While killing Moriah Wilson was truly good for Armstrong, at least in the moment if not in the aftermath, I personally disapprove of Armstrong killing Moriah Wilson and I view the act as murder." Rather, I am saying "Just as the world works such that, for example, light travels faster than sound, the world works such that Armstrong's killing of Moriah Wilson was bad, wrong, mistaken, incorrect – a failure."
 
The goals related to flourishing are so typical and obvious that we often assume that people have them. Indeed, if someone did not have the goal of living well, not going to prison, avoiding suffering, and so on, that would be hard to believe. Certainly, I have these goals, so if I were to murder someone in a similar fashion as Armstrong did, I would be failing my goals.
 
So there is a risk of goal-projection here: When someone says that a person ought not have done something, they may be projecting their own goals onto whoever is the subject of their moral criticism. Maybe Armstrong's goal was purely "kill Moriah." Relative to the goal of killing Moriah, Armstrong should kill Moriah. But how does the goal of killing Moriah relate to Armstrong's more fundamental goals? If the goal of killing Moriah fails to further a more fundamental goal, then the goal of killing Moriah is not a goal worth pursuing. Succeeding in that goal would be to fail in a more important one.
 
So we must distinguish which goals we are talking about: 
 
(1) Killing Moriah Wilson fails to further Armstrong's goals (immediate and/or ultimate).
 
(2) Killing Moriah Wilson fails to further my goals related to flourishing and I am projecting my goals onto Armstrong.
 
(3) Killing Moriah Wilson fails to further the goals Armstrong would have were she to have the goals a typical person has.
 
(4) Killing Moriah Wilson fails to further the goals Armstrong would have were she to have the goals a wise person would have in her situation.
 
When I make the claim:
 
(S) Kaitlin Armstrong should not have killed Moriah Wilson.
 
Is (1), (2), (3), or (4) the correct interpretation of what I mean?
 
In terms of immediate vs ultimate goals, certainly Armstrong had an immediate goal of killing Wilson, and killing Wilson successfully furthered (achieved) that goal. But given Armstrong's more ultimate goal of not going to prison (etc.), killing Wilson failed with respect to that (those) goal(s).
 
With 'ultimate goal' specified for 1, it's possible for all four interpretations to be correct at the same time. All four can be objectively true.
 
Interpretation (2) by itself does not secure the truth of S; if (2) is the only correct interpretation of S when I utter S, then S is false and, to preserve its truth, must be changed to:
 
(S2) I should not kill Moriah Wilson (within the same or similar context in which Armstrong killed Wilson).
 
So to argue that S is true is to argue that (1), (3), or (4) is true. 
 
But now reconsider:
 
(W) Kaitlin Armstrong killing Moriah Wilson was wrong (incorrect, not right, mistaken, evil).
 
What is the wrong-maker here? One option is that the wrong-maker is the failure to further a goal in one of the above senses. But I can't make sense of an objective notion of 'wrong' in any way other than the same wrongness as when someone holds a false belief.  
  
So a better option is that the wrong-maker is the false belief behind Armstrong's action, or any false belief that Armstrong is committed to in virtue of performing the action. What is Armstrong's held or committed false belief behind her choice to kill Wilson? A number of possibilities: 
 
"This is worth doing"
"The goodness of this action outweighs its badness"
"This action maximizes flourishing"
"This will make the world a better place" 
"This will make me happy in the long-term"
"This will make me happier than I would be otherwise" 
"This will further my ultimate goals"
"I won't regret this"
 
If Armstrong's ultimate goal is in fact: "Kill Moriah Wilson", then interpretation (1) is false. But a) It seems impossible for that to be Armstrong's ultimate goal, and b) Even if it were Armstrong's ultimate goal, the truth of interpretations (2)–(4) is preserved.
 
But it seems to me that the problem with interpretation (2) can be extended to interpretations (3) and (4). That is, to preserve the truth of (3) and (4), we'd need to similarly change them, respectively, to:
 
(S3) A typical person should not kill Moriah Wilson (within the same or similar context in which Armstrong killed Wilson).
 
(S4) A wise person should not kill Moriah Wilson (within the same or similar context in which Armstrong killed Wilson)
 
If this is right, then for S to be true, interpretation (1) needs to be true. While it's impossible to know what Armstrong believed at the time of the murder, it seems nearly certain that she believed in false beliefs or was committed to false beliefs at the time as noted above, and it's the wrongness of these false beliefs that grounds the wrongness of the action. So even if interpretations (2)–(4) fail to secure the truth of S, interpretation (1) is easily defended.
 
Someone might wonder what difference there might be in claiming that Kaitlin Armstrong killing Moriah Wilson was wrong versus Kaitlin Armstrong killing Moriah Wilson was evil.
 
My answer is that 'evil' in this context just means 'wrong' (mistaken, incorrect, holding false beliefs or being committed to false beliefs) within a moral context—a context of consequences, intentions, and virtues—where the happiness, pain, flourishing, and suffering of experiencers is at stake. We especially associate 'evil' with someone's intentions and character; so Kaitlin Armstrong killing Moriah Wilson was evil = Kaitlin Armstrong killing Moriah Wilson in the context in which she did betrays Armstrong's vicious character and intentions.
 
Part 3: Clarifying thoughts around goals and 'should' statements
 
When a typical person says "X person should not have done Y", it's not clear what interpretation they would point out as their intended meaning. For all I know, most people don't care about what a person's actual ultimate goals are and instead care mainly about what a person's ultimate goal would be if that person were smart, well-informed, empathetic, and had true beliefs about the goodness and badness of things. So something like interpretation (4) might be a more popular interpretation. The problem with landing on interpretation (1) as I have is that the truth of "X person should not have done Y" literally depends on that person's actual ultimate goals. So consider:
 
(H) Hitler should not have systematically killed millions of Jews.
 
If Hitler's ultimate goal required systematically killing millions of Jews, then H is false under interpretation (1). It's plausible that Hitler's ultimate goals were something like "maximize flourishing for humanity", in which case H is true under interpretation (1). But let's explore what happens when interpretation (1) is false.
 
When it comes to the truth of 'should' statements we have to keep goal-relativity in mind, and while 'should' statements depend on goals, we can argue that some goals are better than others. Even if H is false relative to Hitler's goals, Hitler's goals were themselves insane and evil. So H can be reinterpreted as:
 
(H*) Hitler should not have had goals that required the systematic killing of millions of Jews. 
 
Again, because 'should' statements only make sense in the context of some goal, H* can only be true if there is some more fundamental goal of which the subgoal of systematic killing of millions of Jews fails to further, but that might not apply in Hitler's case. So we have to reinterpret farther:
 
(Hm) Hitler's goals were based on misunderstandings about race, about human flourishing, about the goodness and badness of things, and so on. 
 
(H**) Imagine Hitler had goals that were not based on these misunderstandings. Relative to these goals, Hitler should not have systematically killed millions of Jews.
 
But not only should Hitler not systematically kill millions of Jews relative to goals not based on misunderstandings, Hitler could not have done so if he had had different goals. Given that Hitler did in fact kill millions of Jews, Hitler did in fact have at least immediate goals that required the killing of millions of Jews. H** has us imagine a counterfactual (Hitler having different goals than he did) the truth of which is not relevant to the truth of H (as the truth of H depends on Hitler's actual goals under interpretation (1)).
 
I agree that the word 'should' is often interpreted as approval. So if I say "Hitler should have systematically killed millions of Jews", it sounds like I'm saying "I approve of Hitler systematically killing millions of Jews." But that's not what I'm saying at all. What I'm saying is "Killing millions of Jews furthered Hitler's ultimate goals, and not killing millions of Jews would have failed to further Hitler's ultimate goals." But I would also say "I do not approve of Hitler's ultimate goals" and that "Hitler's ultimate goals were based on misunderstandings."
 
So (H) Hitler should not have systematically killed millions of Jews is not necessarily true in the sense that systematically killing millions of Jews failed to further Hitler's ultimate goals, but is true in the sense that (Hm) Hitler's goals were based on misunderstandings about race, about human flourishing, about the goodness and badness of things, and so on and that systematically killing millions of Jews fails to further the goals of a person whose goals are not based on such misunderstandings.
 
So when it comes to:
 
(Hw) Hitler was wrong to systematically kill millions of Jews.
 
Hitler wasn't necessarily wrong in the sense of holding or being committed to false beliefs relative to how systematically killing millions of Jews will further his ultimate goals, but Hitler was wrong in the sense of holding or being committed to false beliefs when it comes to the goals themselves. The wrongness of the beliefs, either held or committed to, that ground Hitler's goals grounds the wrongness of the actions taken to further those goals.
 
Part 4: Intrinsic goods ⟶ Value facts ⟶ Descriptive moral realism
 
Quoting the Substack post: "To my mind realists have a very strange psychology. It’s as if they don’t intrinsically disvalue suffering itself - rather they only instrumentally disvalue it insofar as it’s out of accord with the stance-independent moral facts."
 
This is a curious thing to say, because I would think that it's the intrinsic badness of pain and intrinsic goodness of happiness that provides an argument for axiological realism—the view that there are objective value facts—which in turn provides an argument for some kind of moral realism (not necessarily a "categorical imperative / irreducible normative property" kind of moral realism, which I don't accept, but a descriptive kind of moral realism where moral facts are grounded in value facts, which are themselves descriptive).
 
(It's also a curious thing to say because it sounds like the author is saying that realists who "only instrumentally disvalue pain insofar as it's out of accord with stance-independent moral facts" are making an objective mistake about value. So are there objective mistakes about value? If yes, then isn't that an objective value fact?) 
 
Consider what Sharon Rawlette says (The Feeling of Value, Dudley & White, 2016):
 
"Pain is the most frequently cited example of something that is objectively, intrinsically bad. The badness of torture . . . is probably the moral value the most easily agreed upon and the most frequently appealed to in arguments for the self-evidence of certain moral truths. There is something about the experience of pain that convinces many people of moral realism. . . . I believe that part of the usual phenomenology of pain is an instantiation of the phenomenal quality of undesirability—of badness—and that instantiation of this quality is bad no matter what judgments anyone makes about it. Experience of this quality is what I believe leads many people to assert with such confidence that pain is objectively bad." (75)
 
She then goes on to defend the idea that there is a quale of badness. Shockingly, some philosophers attack the notion of intrinsic badness. But I won't go into that here. Because the topic at hand is subjectivism, a subjectivist can agree that there really is a quale of badness, but will want to say that it is only subjectively true that pain is intrinsically bad. Indeed, they might say that the notion of intrinsicality used here necessarily includes the notion of subjectivity. How could pain be objectively bad?
 
Rawlette helps us untangle what it means to say something is objectively bad:
 
"On my view, moral facts are not mind-independent. They are quite dependent on whether people are in the mental states of pleasure or pain. . . . However, on my view and on these other realist views, facts about the goodness of pleasure and the badness of pain . . . are judgment-independent. These views say . . . pain is pro-tanto bad, and . . . this badness . . . exists independently of whether anyone judges it to be there." (15)
 
So the subjectivist is right that my pain is subjective in the sense that my pain depends on my subjectivity; my pain depends on my mind. More generally, goodness and badness depends on minds. But whether an instance of pleasure or pain has the qualities it does, that doesn't depend on anyone's judgment, not even on the judgment of the subject of that pleasure or pain. Experiences are pre-judgment; indeed, where could our judgments come from, or be based on, if not our experiences? The truth of the statement "Chocolate tastes good" is judgment-dependent (put another way: its truth is relative), but the experience of chocolate tasting good is not judgment-dependent (and the truth that such an experience took place and had the qualities it had is absolute and not relative).
 
Case in point, even if animals are not capable of the kinds of evaluative judgments that we humans make, the pain of animals still has the quality that it does, including the quality of badness.
 
Part 5: Truthseeker objection to anti-realism and the problem of undergenerated reasons
 
Quoting the Substack post: "I find the idea that my goals must somehow be ordained by the universe in order to act on them profoundly bizarre."
 
When I hear this, alarm bells go off in my head. I'm sensitive to any anti-truth sentiments; being a genuine truthseeker, in my mind, comes first above all things in philosophy.
 
A (perhaps not-so-charitable) interpretation of this might be:
 
"I find the idea that I ought to act according to what's true profoundly bizarre."
 
Or:
 
"I find the idea that I ought to be bothered by the fact that my actions are based on false beliefs profoundly bizarre."
 
I worry that anti-realist views imply that an omniscient, perfectly rational person who acts purely according to the facts can commit atrocities, say, a mass shooting. I'm convinced that an omniscient, perfectly rational person who acts purely according to the facts cannot commit a mass shooting. (Call this the "truthseeker objection" to anti-realism, an objection I have yet to see a good response to.)
 
This brings me back to the question of why I disapprove of Armstrong's murder of Wilson. As I understand it, this gets to the "undergeneration of reasons" objection to moral anti-realism (see: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reasons-internal-external/#UndArg – strictly speaking this relates to internal vs external reasons, though reasons themselves relate to realism vs anti-realism).
 
Consider a bus driver who drives children to an elementary school each morning during the school semester. The bus driver is aware that there is a cliff near the school, and that if the driver wanted, they could, one morning, drive the bus off the cliff and kill themselves and all the children inside.
 
Nearly all bus drivers nearly all the time would not choose to do this given the chance. Question: Why not? Why wouldn't drive the bus off the cliff killing myself and dozens of children in the process given the chance?
 
Explanation 1: Evolution. Evolution selects for pro-survival, pro-social behaviors and attitudes, and that explains why I have the pro-survival and pro-social behavior of not driving the bus off a cliff.
 
Explanation 2: Social programming. I have been raised by loving parents and a healthy social and psychological environment, instilling within me a strong sense of empathy, compassion, and a desire to do the right thing. Maybe I've been indoctrinated to believe that evil people go to hell when they die, or that only good people go to heaven when they die. So out of fear of hell, or desire for heaven, or out of empathy and compassion, or a desire to make my parents proud or what have you, any of these things can explain why I wouldn't drive the bus off the cliff.
 
As far as I can tell (an anti-realist can correct me if I'm mistaken), anti-realists take it for granted that something like explanation 1 or 2 (or both) must be true and that's all there is to say about why people do what they do. This undergenerates reasons. There's another explanation, one that I introspect and see to be true in my case (and perhaps true in addition to aspects of explanations 1 and/or 2):
 
Explanation 3: Sight. I see how goodness and badness work. I see how death is a depriving evil, depriving the one who dies from future good experiences. I see how my death would deprive me from future good experiences, and how the deaths of the children would deprive them of future good experiences. I see how I don't know what the future of these children holds, or how much they will suffer or flourish, and so I cannot assume that these deaths would save more than deprive. I see how flourishing works like a web, and how our actions reverberate like ripples in a pond, and how the deaths of these children would tear apart their families and their communities, and would even bring a touch of despair to strangers who hear the story. I understand the intrinsic badness of pain, and the sheer pain of loss, grief, and lost optimism that would occur for the surviving families, leaving wounds that would never truly heal. I understand the goodness of flourishing and the badness of suffering, and by this understanding I have the goal to maximize goodness and minimize suffering. I understand how driving the bus off the cliff would fail to further this goal, and by this I understand why it's true that I ought not drive the bus off the cliff, and I understand why denying this truth is to say something false; its truth is not relative and does not depend on anyone's judgment.
 
This might lead to an argument in favor of external reasons, with an external reason being a theoretical answer to a 'why' question that would answer the question in a true and relevant way grounded in truths external to one's own feelings.
 
Given the 'why' question "Why don't you drive the bus off a cliff?", I could answer "Because I don't feel like it", and while that answer might be true and relevant, it wouldn't be grounded in truths external to my feelings. But the answer given under Explanation 3 is grounded in truths external to my feelings: truths about the goodness and badness of things and about what experiences certain people would have under different circumstances.
 
If an anti-realist says "There are no external reasons", and by that they mean "If someone is asked 'Why don't you drive the bus off a cliff', they will not be able to give a true and relevant answer grounded in truths external to personal feelings", then the anti-realist says something false. I can, and just did, give a true and relevant answer grounded in truths external to my personal feelings to that question.
 
In conclusion, when I say "X action is wrong", I am not primarily making a claim about my own personal preferences, values, likes, dislikes, opinions, or feelings. I am claiming to recognize the truth of the goodness and badness of the actions involved, whether and how an action furthers a goal, and the truth of the falsity of the beliefs that ground the actions and goals involved. These truths remain true regardless of anyone's judgment. It is from this recognition that my disapproval originates, and I can introspect and see that this recognition is part of, and even primary to, the explanation as to why I disapprove of the actions I conclude to be wrong. Explanations of my disapproval that don't include my recognition of external truths undergenerate reasons for my disapproval.

Thursday, July 10, 2025

An objectively true value fact that is certainly true

Sometimes I see anti-realist YouTube comments say something like: "Give me ONE example of an objectively true moral fact. I'll wait 😏" 

I don't know about moral fact, but here's an objectively true value fact:

AGONY: If life were nothing but a series of agonizing moments, then it would be better to not be alive.

If someone says "It's better to be alive and experience an endless number of agonizing moments than to be dead" or if they say "It's a toss-up between experiencing an endless number of agonizing moments and being dead", then they have said something false. AGONY is true independently of anyone's judgment of its truth. That's an objective truth.

AGONY is not, however, mind-independently true. Value depends on consciousness, so of course value facts depend on minds. But, as Sharon Rawlette points out in her book The Feeling of Value, what we care about when discussing objectivity is not mind-dependence, but judgment- (aka stance-) dependence. Something can be mind-dependently true while being stance-independently true. Consider the following exchange:

P1: "Wow, I had a great time last night!"

P2: "No you didn't."

End scene. That P1 had a great time last night is mind-dependently true, and because it is in fact true that P1 had a great time last night, P2 says something false about P1's experience. P2's stance has no bearing whatsoever on the truth of P1's experience.

So for every phenomenal fact—a fact of experience—that fact is mind-dependently yet stance-independently true. The facts a) that the experience took place when it did and b) that the experience had the quality it had do not depend on judgment.

The anti-realist might try to argue that AGONY is judgment-dependent. To judge one thing as better than another always involves... a judgment! The reason why, the anti-realist might say, it would sound so strange to hear someone say "It's better to be alive and experience an endless number of agonizing moments than to be dead" is because that's a judgment no one (or virtually no one) would make. But just because AGONY is an "inevitable" judgment doesn't change the fact that it is in fact a judgment. In theory, if someone were to judge "It's better to be alive and experience an endless number of agonizing moments than to be dead", then that judgment would be true for the person who judges as such. So AGONY is a judgment-dependent claim. (An anti-realist could argue that AGONY is not true in a judgment-dependent or judgment-independent way because it's not a real proposition, but an expression of emotion. But I take emotivism to be obviously false so I'll move on.)

But this fails to explain why AGONY is an inevitable judgment. It's inevitable because it's not a judgment but a conjunction of phenomenal facts; pain has as part of its essence a not-worth-it quality while happiness has as part of its essence a worth-it quality. Pain, by virtue of what it is, makes life less worth living while happiness, by virtue of what it is, makes life more worth living. (Some pains are worth it exactly because they are necessary for certain kinds of happiness.) This not-worth-it-ness (or, badness) and worth-it-ness (or, goodness) of pain and happiness respectively is found in the phenomenal experience itself of pain and happiness. So goodness and badness are directly accessible via immediate experience. 

So we directly access the badness of pain, we directly access the goodness of happiness, and therefore we directly access the phenomenal preferableness of happiness over pain. Therefore, happiness being better than pain is not grounded in a judgment, but is grounded in immediate experience. The concept 'better' is itself not grounded in judgment, but in experience.

I could not possibly deny AGONY because the badness of pain is basic and self-evident, the goodness of happiness is basic and self-evident, and the preferableness of happiness to pain is basic and self-evident. The self-evident, experience-based truth of AGONY, that a life that is nothing but a series of agonizing moments is not worth living, is why it's impossible to deny.

I think this gets at what might be at bottom the most fundamental disagreement between realists and anti-realists, which is whether pain is bad independently of judgment and whether happiness is good independently of judgment. The realist claims there is no judgment here, only immediate experience, while the anti-realist claims that while there might be immediate experience of some of the qualities of pain and happiness, you cannot immediately experience badness or goodness itself, and in fact what is taken to be an experience of badness or goodness is really an interpretation of one's immediate experience.

But, quoting Rawlette:

"In sum, normative phenomenology often comes to be associated with other properties or objects. This can lead us to assume that a feeling of goodness or badness must always be about something further. But normative phenomenology can stand all on its own, and it does not lose its intrinsic normative character in doing so. When normative phenomenology is isolated, as seems to happen in cases of electrical stimulation of certain limbic areas, its positive or negative nature stands out clearly as a property of the phenomenology itself and not of any intentional object. This means that, even if it is clear that our normative phenomenology cannot be taken as evidence of the objective goodness or badness of other objects, our normative phenomenology itself may nevertheless be objectively good or bad." (pg 98)

Response 1: I don't agree that the goodness of happiness and the badness of pain are intrinsically normative like Rawlette claims. I do agree that they are intrinsically worth having and not worth having respectively. I say this because normativity is attached to the concepts of 'ought' and 'should', and indeed Rawlette describes happiness as having an intrinsic ought-to-be-ness, which I take to basically mean the same thing as having an intrinsic normativity. But 'oughts' and 'shoulds' I think are not irreducible properties but can be analyzed in terms of mistakes, failures, successes, and goals. It doesn't seem true to me that my happiness, or anyone's happiness, ought to be, even though it is good. So I feel free to translate this notion of 'ought-to-be-ness' as 'worth-having-ness' or 'worthiness'. Joys (instances of happiness) make life more worth living while pains make life less worth living in virtue of what they are. I don't see how joys ought to be in virtue of what they are or how pains ought not be in virtue of what they are. Indeed, if 'oughts' must be analyzed in terms of goals, and if one's goal is to maximize happiness in an idealized way, then certain joys ought not be promoted (e.g. entertainment at the cost of productivity) and certain pains ought to be embraced (e.g. the pain of serious effort). While Rawlette speaks of pro tanto ought-to-be-ness, I cannot make sense of this idea. I can make sense of the idea of pro tanto worthiness. But given a goal, one action is either the best at furthering that goal / is necessary to further that goal, or not, and so you either ought to perform that action or not relative to that goal. I don't see oughts as coming in degrees.

Response 2: In context, Rawlette is discussing the fact that experiences of happiness and pain are so strongly correlated with objects or events that we can easily make the mistake in thinking that the goodness of our happiness or the badness of our pain is about those objects or events. But that's not true. There are studies where patients have their brains stimulated and they report feelings of euphoria. Per Rawlette, this shows that at least in principle there are experiences of happiness that aren't about anything or directed at any object or event causing the happiness.

But 1) That seems debatable, given that the euphoria the patients experience is arguably about a) their brain being in the state that it's in, and/or b) the event of the brain stimulation.

But this is too quick, because you could ask the patient, "What are you so happy about?" and they might say "I don't know!", showing that the patient is happy about nothing in particular.

But I can imagine someone who defends representationalism of the mind pushing back against this and saying just because a person doesn't know what their qualia is representing, that doesn't mean their qualia isn't representing something, in this case representing a certain internal state or event.

So I'm not convinced that these experiments show that our happiness/pain isn't about something.   

And 2) Rawlette doesn't cite any studies. A quick search reveals at least one study: Okun et al 2004, published online 2010, in Neurocase. In that study a single patient reported euphoria during deep brain stimulation. So on just a first glance, apparently euphoria can be induced through brain stimulation.

But 3) If happiness/pain lack aboutness, shouldn't we be able to see that directly? If the goodness of happiness is phenomenal, then doesn't that settle the question? Don't all raw feelings lack aboutness? When reflecting on the appearance of redness, the appearance of the appearance and the reality of the appearance are one and the same. The appearance-reality distinction breaks down when it comes to appearances themselves. You cannot have an appearance of redness without having a phenomenal experience of redness, as the two are the same. That appearance is not about anything; there's no propositional content to it, it's just an experience. The same applies to pain: You cannot appear, from a first-person perspective, to be in pain without actually being in pain. The internal appearance of pain and pain are the same thing. And the badness (the not-worth-it quality) of pain is part of that experience, and so the badness is likewise not about anything.

This generalizes to all "phenomenally defined" terms. If you asked me to define what 'red' means to a person blind from birth, there are no words I can use to communicate phenomenal red. Same with 'pain'. I cannot define phenomenal pain to a robot that doesn't know what it is. This is why 'good' and 'bad' are so hard to define; first, these words are used in different ways, requiring careful analysis in breaking them down, and second, at the core they are phenomenal terms which cannot be defined with words, only with experience.

So an even simpler claim than AGONY would be:

BAD: This pain is bad. Or: That pain was bad.

Laurence BonJour describes what we allegedly have immediate access to (Epistemology, 2nd ed., pg 100-101):

"What things are we supposed to be immediately aware of or 'acquainted' with . . .? . . . Descartes' view is apparently that we are immediately aware of the existence and contents of all of our conscious states of mind, a view that has been adopted by many others. These would include, first, sensory experiences of the sort that we have just been discussing . . . Included also would be, second, bodily sensations, such as itches, pains, tingles, and the like. These are naturally regarded as experiences of various events and processes in the physical body, but Descartes' point again would be that there is in each of these cases something directly or immediately present to consciousness, something that cannot be doubted, even though the more remote bodily cause certainly can be. The third main category of states of whose existence and content we are allegedly immediately aware are conscious instances of what are sometimes referred to as 'propositional attitudes': conscious beliefs or acceptances of propositions, together with conscious wonderings, fearings, doubtings, desirings, intendings, and so forth, also having propositional content. In these cases, the view would be that I am immediately aware both of the propositional content . . . and of the distinctive attitude toward that content that such a state involves . . ."

So, if this view about direct access is right, not only do I have direct access to conscious states, including experiences, but I would even have direct access to the propositional content of BAD along with direct access to my acceptance (or rejection) of BAD (i.e. whether a particular mental state of mine can be expressed as BAD).

And as Rawlette brings to mind, how could it be possible that I be aware of the idea of badness? Rawlette suggests that it is exactly phenomenal badness that explains where we get the concept.

"When we ask ourselves what it is we mean by 'goodness,' we can turn to this basic phenomenal experience for the answer." (100) 

Continuing:

"While a particular person's judgments or attitudes will determine whether he or she feels a positive or a negative quale, the positive or negative nature of the phenomenology is intrinsic to the phenomenology itself. If a particular person feels a negative quale, no one can experience that same quale and have it be positive rather than negative." (99) 

And:

"When we stop trying to project the qualities of normative phenomenology onto perceptions with which they are merely associated, we realize that, far from being an illusion, judgment-independent value exists in the realm most immediate to us. Judgment-independent value exists as part of the very fabric of our mental life." (100) 

So not only is the badness of pain not a judgment, interpretation, or theoretical posit, but the badness of pain is pre-judgment, pre-interpretation, and pre-theory. The badness of pain is not a posit to explain data, but is itself data, and data of an incorrigible kind (directly accessible). 

Whenever there is judgment, there is a gap that allows for error. But when you have a phenomenal-noumenal collapse, something pre-judgment, there is no possibility of error. Compare: "I remember that I had lentils and rice for breakfast" to "I had lentils and rice for breakfast." What is certainly true is that I have a memory or a memory experience. But when I interpret that memory of having had lentils and rice for breakfast as entailing that I actually had lentils and rice for breakfast, that's where memory is not perfectly reliable. It may have been the day before yesterday that I had lentils and rice, and I'm misremembering and thinking it was today. This is generally true of introspection: Introspective beliefs constituted by phenomenal experience are incorrigible, but when I use those beliefs to interpret a further conclusion, that inferred belief is not incorrigible. This is why Descartes' cogito "I think, therefore I am" contains an error (a mistake I don't think Descartes himself made, but is found in the common Latin and English translations); it should say I see that I am. There is no 'therefore', there is no inference.

Thus, Josh Rasmussen (Who Are You, Really? 27 & 29 fn8): 

"My analysis of eliminativism, then, is fundamentally this: by the light of introspection, I think it is possible to know something about your experiences directly. In particular, you can know some thoughts, feelings, and intentions. On this analysis, the subjective aspects of consciousness are not theoretical posits that explain some data . . . Rather, conscious states are part of your data—which I think you can access directly."

". . . in my analysis, a belief based directly and solely on a direct experience is the most secure a belief could possibly be, for it has the fewest sources of possible error. . . . necessarily, if one directly experiences x . . . and on that basis alone believes that x exists, then that belief is true."

Sunday, March 23, 2025

Sharon Rawlette on antirealism

"[If antirealism were true] I don't know why I would care about ethics anymore, why I would care about being systematic about the way that I choose what things I'm going to do, or even care about having ethical debates with people. We're not talking about anything real. So you care about people in this difficult situation and I don't, and that's as far as we can go."
 
80,000 hours podcast #138, 14m. (Classic Episode)
 
"It's not that the goodness or badness of this state [of happiness or pain] supervenes on it, but that intrinsic goodness is a qualitative state, so it's something that you can observe and experience yourself. If we didn't ever experience pleasure or pain, we wouldn't have the concept of intrinsic goodness that we do in fact have and use when making moral decisions. When we experience pleasure or pain, what we experience is something that justifies the desire or justifies avoiding a certain thing. In the book I talk about the feeling of ought-to-be-ness. When you feel pleasure, you're like 'Oh, this is why life is worth living. This is what we're here for. This is worth having.' And when you're experiencing suffering, you're experience something that – if this were all there was to existence, it would be better to be dead." (19-20m)
 
"How do we even have a concept of moral facts? We have it through these experiences. We can experience their value or their disvalue. How can we experience the truth or falsity of moral facts? We can directly experience intrinsic goodness or intrinsic badness, that's something directly present to our consciousness, and then from there we can use the information that we have about the world that we live in to determine which other things are instrumentally good and bad because of the way they produce this conscious experience." (21m)
 
"I think that that's generally true [that you cannot derive an ought from an is], that's true for every kind of fact about the world except in these particular experiences of pleasure and pain – I think we see that those two categories come together. You can't describe what it is for an experience to be pleasure without talking about its goodness. It wouldn't be pleasure if it wasn't good! And pain would not be pain if it wasn't bad." (22-23m)